От Пуденко Сергей
К Пуденко Сергей
Дата 06.01.2006 17:31:15
Рубрики Интернет & общество;

Арсенал 21 века. Some remarks on historical-libidinal materialism ("Ибимат".)



1) спецкурс по теме Ибимата (много) и
2) - развитие темы "общества Контроля" (первая статья Делеза "Контроль и Становление" - в Альманахе и на первой странице сайта)
Майкл Хардт - соавтор "Империи", с Негри.

к сожалению, ЭТИ вводные тексты пока только по-английски

-----
http://www.protevi.com/john/DG/
Some remarks on historical-libidinal materialism

Comments and Questions to: {John Protevi}
{LSU French Studies}
{Protevi Home Page}


Last week we discussed one wing of contemporary French philosophy, the post-phenomenological philosophy of radical difference. This week I'll lecture on the other wing, the one to which Foucault and Deleuze/Guattari belong, historical-libidinal materialism. Terminologically, hist-lib mat is often called a "post-structuralism," so we'll begin with structuralism.


Structuralism

Structuralism is in some sense the polar opposite of phenomenology. Cultural meaning is grounded in social structures, not subjects. There's a good sense in which Foucault's work in the 60s is akin to structuralism, although he will vehemently deny that he IS a "structuralist" in the preface to the English edition of OT.

Structuralism was a widespread "movement" of 20th C thought, reaching its peak in 50s-60s France. Notable figures are Ferdinand de Saussure, Roman Jakobson, Noam Chomsky in linguistics; Claude Lйvi-Strauss in anthropology; Jacques Lacan in psychoanalysis; Jean Piaget in developmental psychology; and Roland Barthes in literary criticism.

Hallmarks of structuralist thought, according to Piaget (Structuralism: NY: Basic Books, 1970): wholeness, transformation, self-regulation. 1) wholeness: the usual opposition is between emergent properties vs. atomistic compounding of prior and independent elements; Piaget however prefers "operational structuralism" = focus on relations [on processes by which whole comes about], not on whole OR on elements. Problem of genesis is key point. 2) transfomations: laws of composition of structures are simultaneously structuring and structured: they structure the system actively, but they can only be ("passively") defined in terms of that system (they are "structured"). 3) self-regulation: self-maintenance and closure. In math/logic, by operations; in social systems by feedback (regulation); in biological systems by rhythm.

Let's look at social systems, primarily at Levi-Strauss. Piaget begins by distinguishing global from analytic structuralism. Global structuralism studies emergent wholes; analytic structuralism elicits deep structures of transformational laws that explain empirical systems; structures are not facts but logico-math models that explain facts (thus social actors are unaware of deep rules that explain social actions.)

Piaget describes L-S as being "the very incarnation of the structuralist faith in the permanence of human nature and the unity of reason," (106) and quotes him as writing, "all social life, however elementary, presupposes an intellectual activity in man of which the formal properties cannot, accordingly, be a reflection of the concrete organization of society" (Totemism, 96; quoted on 107). It is this "unconscious conceptual structure" of societies that L-S seeks to discover, locating it between infrastructure and superstructure in the Marxist senses.

L-S is firmly synchronic: history is only the holding-pen of elements of structures, the starting point for the quest for intelligibility. L-S was inspired by linguistics, but the real take-off for him was being able to give mathematical form to social systems.

The ontological status of these structures is problematic. Piaget offers the following: "the collective intellect is the social equilibrium resulting from the interplay of the operations that enter into all cooperation. ... [I]ntelligence ... is the equilibriated form of all cognitive functions " (114).

Summary of structuralism: 1). linguistics: emphasis on the code as prior to the message; 2) reduction of content and history; 3) reduction of subjectivity to effect; 4) differential production of meaning; 5) "Kantianism w/o TUA": conditions of possibility of unified meaningful experience; 6) synoptic gaze on totality: structures as self-sufficient; 7) system of transformations governed by self-regulating laws.
Post-structuralism

The study of bodies politic

If structuralism was, in the words of Paul Ricoeur, "Kantianism without the transcendental subject," - a search for structures of intelligibility located in cultural systems rather than in a subject - then post-structuralism is the French response to German philosophy after Kant, that is, to Hegel. In other words, post-structuralism as historical-libidinal materialism turns Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud against Hegel.

Why against Hegel? Because he offers a total history: nothing can exceed or resist the march of spirit. This emphasis on totality, endemic to Western philosophy and science, is shared by the structuralists. Structuralism was expanded by Lйvi-Strauss to the structuralist study of cultural systems in general: all human endeavor. Using the chess analogy common to structuralist self-explication, we can say that structuralism elucidates the synchronic oppositional rules that render a game (language or cultural system) intelligible to an observer, though not to its pieces (speakers or actors): the knight or bishop can know what is expected of him, but not understand the totality of the "rules of the game." The structuralist will model these rules using the oppositions in which each piece fits: the knight, which is not the bishop, moves one way, while the bishop, which is not the knight, moves another way.

To arrive at a structure of intelligibility via oppositions between rules governing pieces, the structuralist observer-modeller practices a grand meta-opposition between internal structure and external history. Hence the historical forces that produced different social actors (the bodily training of real knights and bishops) in order to fulfill social aims - e.g., the production and distribution of surplus value - are neutralized into rules that produce intelligibility for an observer.

Here we see the arena for historical-libidinal materialism: the production of bodies. For post-structuralism, cultural oppositions rely on the forceful production of bodies trained to fulfill the expectations of the group into which they are placed. In other words, the great social oppositions which render a system intelligible to a structuralist observer: male/female, adult/child, white/black, owner/worker, are for post-structuralism the result of appropriately-behaving and -labelled bodies produced by such loci of historical forces as families, schools, churches, and workplaces.

The historical-libidinal materialism of post-structuralism thus analyzes the de-centered, multiple, conflictual, and overlapping differential and historical force networks productive of "bodies politic": the medicalized, disciplined, racialized, gendered, capitalized - the objectified and subjectified - bodies of people and the body politic of corporations, families, sects, gangs, classes, genders, races, nations, Reichs.

German Predecessors: Marx, Nietzsche, Freud

Despite DG's and Foucault's hatred of the PCF and the Eastern bloc--their hatred of totalitarianism--and Foucault's relegation of Marx's political economy to the 19th century episteme, Marx's term "historical materialism" is still a useful term for much of Foucault's work in DP and HS 1 and DG in AO and MP.

Marx showed how networks of differential force, the material and social relations of production, produce the seemingly natural identities of social categories: "owner," "worker," "product," "tool," etc. What seems a stable unity is the product of an historically relative system of production, a system put in place by the revolutionary force of the bourgeoisie. The productivity of the network of historical labor is masked by the seeming solidity of the thing and the vampiric "productivity" of capital, which Marx showed was simply the coagulation of past labor. [D/G break with Marx here on the notion of "machinic surplus value."] Marx's insistence on dissolving the certainties and identities of everyday common sense by reference to networks of historical force reveals a "deconstructive" Marx purged of the eschatological promises of the inevitability of "The Revolution" into which he sometimes lapsed in his popular addresses and on which the PCF "bureaucrats of the revolution" pounced as if scripture.

Despite their surface opposition on political issues, Nietzsche has some striking similarities to the Marx we sketched above, for Nietzsche also dissolved received pieties through analyses of their construction by historical forces. Simply put, both thinkers are historical materialists; they both show material forces producing identities--in Nietzsche's case the identity of the responsible individual, as in On the Genealogy of Morals. Crudely put, then, Marx dissolves "objective" identity and Nietzsche "subjective" identity by reference to historical force networks.

I have used the term "historical-libidinal materialism" to discuss the Foucualt and D/G wing. To appreciate the libidinal qualification, we turn to Freud. It's often said that there are two Freuds, the scientific materialist of the drives (the "energetic Freud") and the investigative hermeneut of the unconscious (the "linguistic Freud"); the struggle to articulate the two is notoriously difficult, both for Freud himself and his interpreters.

The key for post-structuralism is to distinguish Freud's diagnosis of the patriarchal etiology of the neuroses from his prescriptions for their treatment. In the working out of his diagnoses through his case studies, Freud points to the historical, political, economic and social milieu of his patients, even if his thematic focus on family dynamics often obscured the class and race contributions to the neuroses of his patients those case studies describe. Together with the materialist orientation of the energetic analysis of drives, we see here the elements of a historical-libidinal materialism, which, is brought out in the explicit politicizations of Reich and Deleuze and Guattari.

Although Freud is important in these other post-structuralists, Foucault doesn't have much good to say about him, ultimately implicating Freud in the modern construction of bio-power; DG have a more complex relation, as we will see in reading AO.

20th century French predecessors of post-structuralism

To escape Hegel is the self-acknowledged task of French 20th C thought--to be non-totalizing, non-spiritual, and non-teleological. The French reception of Hegel is very complex: it began in earnest in the late 20s, continued throughout the 30s, and reached a peak in the immediate post-war years. The major figures are Alexandre Kojиve, Jean Hyppolite and Georges Bataille.

The break with Kojиve's anthropological and progressive Hegel, and with Hegel himself, paradoxically begins with the greatest French Hegelian, Jean Hyppolite, who taught and mentored Deleuze, Foucault, and Derrida. (See F's moving tribute in "The Discourse on Language," his speech upon being elected to Hyppolite's chair at the Collиge de France [Appendix to English of AK].) Generally speaking, post-structuralists reject the anthropologism, the historical narrative of progress, and the emphasis on the work of the negative found in Kojиve by taking up the hints in Hyppolite

Hyppolite translated Hegel's Phenomenology (1939-41) and wrote a great commentary, Genesis and Structure of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit (1947). Of more interest to us is Logique et existence (1953), Hyppolite's second major work, which comments on Hegel's Logic. In this work, Hyppolite poses three questions of importance for post-structuralism: non-dialectical difference (diversity rather than opposition), philosophy's appropriation of its other (sense and non-sense), and the centrality, priority, and self-referentiality of language (rather than disembodied thought) in constituting meaning. Hyppolite's locating of language between logic and existence, between thought and bodies, provides the seeds of Foucault's dispositif, which sets forth the relation of discursive and non-discursive practices, and Deleuze's notion of sens, as in the Logique du sens.

Next, Georges Bataille, who attempts a strange interweaving of Nietzsche and Hegel in focusing on communion, sacrifice, waste, intensity, and economy. Bataille's investigations into the construction of the ego or consciousness through social and bodily practices, the converse experience of the dissolution of the ego in madness, the themes of non-productive expenditure, of excess and outrage to common sense, resonate in both Foucault and D/G.

The birth of French historical-libidinal materialism in the 1960s

The key text at the origin of historical-libidinal materialism is Gilles Deleuze's Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962). Here Deleuze shows the productivity of the non-dialectical ("affirmative") differential forces termed by Nietzsche "noble." These forces differentiate themselves first, and only secondarily consider that from which they have differentiated themselves. Deleuze's reading rescued Nietzsche from Heidegger's narrative of the history of metaphysics; the thought of differential force would in turn, in Anti-Oedipus, rescue Marx and Freud from the institutional prisons of their "isms," the orthodox parties and schools that appropriated their charisma.

Through the 60s, while Foucault was writing his archaelogies, Deleuze and Derrida led the way in theorizing a "philosophy of difference." The key is to show difference producing identity, but a non-totalized, non-spiritual, and non-teleological difference--in other words, difference freed of Hegel (and, minus the "spiritual" bit, official Marxism). Key texts: Difference and Repetition and Of Grammatology.

(In)famously, the events of May 1968 accelerated the post-structuralist movement. The story has often been told, but bears repeating. A threshold of social unrest was passed, as turbulent post-war affluence and concomitant life-style experimentation was countered by a government backlash in the guise of education reform. May '68 included students and workers, to the befuddlement of the established guardians of the revolution, the French Communist Party. Days of general strikes and standoffs with the police led de Gaulle to call a general election. Shockingly, de Gaulle's call for a parliamentary solution to the crisis was backed by the Communists, who were evidently as scared of any revolution from below - which by definition would lack the party discipline they so craved - as were the official holders of State power, to whose position they aspired. The worker-student movement eventually collapsed, leaving memories of non-scripted social interactions and revealing the investments of the Party, lampooned thereafter as "bureaucrats of the revolution" (Foucault's Foreword to the English translation of AO).

The response changed French academic life: 1) institutionally, by the creation of Paris VIII (Vincennes) where Foucault was chair briefly, and where Deleuze and Irigaray taught later; and 2) in the direction of the post-structuralist movement. The second change concerns us here. Although it was certainly never apolitical in its first incarnation, the philosophy of difference became (explicitly) political post-1968. It became, in fact, a politics of philosophy dedicated to exposing the historical force relations producing identity in all its ontological and epistemological forms. In other words, post-structuralism now set out to show how the unified objects of the world, the unified subjects who know and hence control them, the unified bodies of knowledge that codify this knowledge, and the unified institution of philosophy that polices the whole affair, are products of historical, political forces in combat with other forces.

The most immediately provocative politicization of the philosophy of difference was Deleuze and Guattari's 1972 Anti-Oedipus. A rip-roaring attack on the tame Marx-Freud synthesis that was the mother's milk of the bureaucrats of the revolution, Anti-Oedipus is historical-libidinal materialism par excellence: the explosive result of using the Nietzschean thought of differential force to expose the production of the socio-political identities of race, class, nation, and - most threateningly - gendered personal identity.

In the mid 70s the politics of philosophy reaches a critical mass, with major works published every year: Derrida's Glas; Lyotard's Libidinal Economy; Irigaray's Speculum of the Other Woman; Cixous and Clйment's The Newly-Born Woman; Kristeva's Revolution in Poetic Language; Foucault's Discipline and Punish; Baudrillard's Symbolic Exchange and Death. All of them to one extent or another show how philosophy has served to legitimate forceful constructions of identity in racial, religious, economic, political, and sexual contexts. By analyzing the interrelations of these registers, and by showing differential force as productive of identity, these works set the stage for Deleuze and Guattari's A Thousand Plateaus (1980), arguably the high-water mark to date of post-structuralism.

In 14 plateaus, or points of intensity - productive connections between forces without reference to an external governing source - Deleuze and Guattari develop a new materialism in which a politicized philosophy of difference joins forces with the sciences explored in Difference and Repetition. A Thousand Plateaus is a book of strange and terrifying new questions: "Who Does the Earth Think It Is?," "How Do You make Yourself a Body Without Organs?," "How does the war-machine ward off the apparatus of capture of the State?" and so on. To over-simplify, Deleuze and Guattari take the insights of "complexity theory", which explores the mathematics of the various thresholds at which matter achieves self-organization (e.g., turbulence or oscillation), and extend the notion of self-organizing matter - matter with no need of transcendent organizing agents such as gods, leaders, capital, or subjects - to the social, linguistic, political, and economic realms. The resultant "rhizome" or de-centered network that is A Thousand Plateaus provides hints for experimentation with the more and more de-regulated flows of energy and matter, ideas and actions - and the attendant attempts at binding them - that make up the contemporary world.

A stunning work, nothing after A Thousand Plateaus by any post-structuralist author has the same potential for inciting new flows of ideas and action. Yet this is not the end of the story. Perhaps the most fruitful area of on-going post-structuralism will prove to be feminism, especially as that work interacts with Foucault, Deleuze, Derrida, Levinas et al.

This interchange is not a simple case of feminism learning from philosophers who remain untouched. Rather we have here a "becoming" in the Deleuzian sense, for both terms change in the encounter: for instance, "Deleuze" or "Derrida" - what those names mean as potentials for inciting flows of ideas and action - are not the same after their encounter with the "corporeal feminism" of Elizabeth Grosz or the theory of performative gender in Judith Butler.


+++++++
2) Общество Контроля


{makeworlds}

The Withering of Civil Society
Submitted by fls on Sun, 04/04/2004 - 16:37.
BY MICHAEL HARDT

Civil society is proposed as an essential feature of any democracy: the institutional infrastructure for political mediation and public exchange. However, while recognizing the democratic functions that the concept and reality of civil society have made possible, it is also important to be aware of the functions of discipline and exploitation that are inherent in and inseparable from these same structures.

Furthermore, we must question whether the social foundations necessary for the construction and sustenance of civil society are themselves present in contemporary social formations. I want to argue, in fact, that in recent years the conditions of possibility for civil society have progressively been undermined in North America, Europe, and elsewhere (if indeed they ever existed outside the European world). ... The society we are living in today is more properly understood as a postcivil society.

Organization of Abstract Labor

In political philosophy, civil society is fundamentally linked to the modern notion of labor, a connection made most clear by G. W. F. Hegel. ... According to Hegel ... through needs, work, exchange, and the pursuit of particular self-interests, the В»unorganized atoms of civil societyВ« are to be ordered toward the universal - not exactly through the mysterious actions of Adam Smith's invisible hand, but rather through the competitive institutions of capitalist production and circulation. ... The second innovation in Hegel's usage of the concept of civil society, which is closely tied to the first but specific to Hegel in its formulation, is the emphasis on the educative aspect of civil society. ... In other words, civil society takes the natural human systems of needs and particular self-interests, puts them in relation with each other through the capitalist social institutions of production and exchange and, thus, on the basis of the mediation and subsumption of the particular, poses a terrain on which the State can realize the universal interest of society in В»the actuality of the ethical IdeaВ«. Hegelian education in civil society is a process of formal subsumption, a process whereby particular differences, foreign to the universal, are negated and preserved in unity.

Hegel combines and highlights these economic and educative aspects in his conception that civil sociey is primarily a society of _labor_. ... In his early writings on the State, in the Jena period, Hegel conceived the process of the abstraction of Iabor from its concrete instantiations as the motor driving the civilizing social institutions. В»Concrete labor is the elemental, substantial conversion,В« the basic foundation of everything, but it is also В»blind and savage,В« that is, uneducated in the universal interest. Concrete labor, which in this early period Hegel imagines as the labor of peasants, is the human activity closest to nature. Just like nature, concrete labor cannot be simply negated, since it is the foundation of all society, but neither can it be simply integrated, since it is savage and uncivilized. ... [W]e should say that civil society is not simply the society of labor, but that it is specifically the society of _abstract_ labor.

This same educative process of abstraction is also at the center of Hegel's mature conception of civil society, which he poses in his later writings in less philosophical, more practical terms: through labor the pursuit of the satisfaction of one's particular needs is related to the pursuits of others and thus В»subjective self-seeking turns into a contribution to the satisfaction of the needs of everyone else.В« Hegel finds this educative role of labor, the transformation to the universal, organized and made explicit in the institutional trade unions, the corporations, which structurally orient the particular interests of workers toward the universal interest of society. Civil society consists of not just the unions but all the institutions of capitalist society that organize abstract labor. ... [C]ivil society is the society of the organization of abstract labor.

Education, Hegemony, Discipline

The Hegelian conception of civil society persists in various forms throughout modern and contemporary social and political theory. When we survey the work of the wide variety of twentieth-century authors who in some form or another take up this notion of civil society, we quickly recognize that the social dialectic of civil society is presented in two guises, one more democratic and the other more authoritarian. Antonio Gramsci has perhaps gone furthest in theorizing the democratic and socialist potential of civil society. ... As we have seen, Hegel conceives the end of social movement and conflict, in both logical and historical terms, as gathered together, subsumed, and thus realized in the ends of State, the actuality of the ethical Idea. Gramsci casts the historical movement or flow in the opposite direction, proposing instead В»that the State's goal is its own end, its own disappearance, in other words, the re-absorption of political society within civil societyВ«. The term _reabsorption_ indicates a reversal of the social flow: what according to the Hegelian process of subsumption flowed from society toward the State now is reversed from the State to civil society as a sort of inverted subsumption. Gramsci is able to understand the process of the withering or disappearance of the State as a process of re-absorption because he conceives the State as existing only secondarily, as if it were a placeholder filling the structural voici left by a not fully developed civil society. When civil society does manage fully to fill its role, the State as such will no longer exist; or rather, State elements will continue to exist only as subordinated agents of civil society's hegemony. ... Expanding and reenforcing the scope and powers of the various segments and institutions of civil society is thus central to a Gramscian strategy of social progress, which will eventually reverse the flow of the Hegelian process and fill the dictatorial and coercive spaces now occupied by the State with democratic forces organized in terms of social hegemony and consent. This hegemony is grounded finally on an Hegelian form of education, which gives the revolutionary class or party its ability to В»absorbВ« or В»assimilate all of societyВ« in the name of general interests. When the State has been effectively subsumed, Gramsci claims, the reign of civil society, or self-government, will begin.

Authors who, like Gramsci, highlight the democratic aspects of civil society focus in general on the pluralism of the institutions of civil society and on the avenues or channels they provide for input into the rule of political society or the State. ... Numerous other strategies of political practice and scholarly analysis ... all emphasize the possibility of democratic representation available through the passages opened by the ideological, cultural, and economic institutions of civil society. From this perspective, the social dialectic in civil society and the possibilities of mediation make the State open to the plurality of social flows channeled through the institutions. The activation of the forces of civil society makes the State porous, destabilize its dictatorial powers or rather В»re-absorbingВ« them within the expanding hegemony of civil society.

In the work of other authors, however, the mediatory institutions that define the relationship between civil society and the State are shown to function not toward democratic but authoritarian ends. From this second perspective, then, the representation of interests through the channels of the institutions does not reveal the pluralistic effects of social forces on the State; instead, it highlights the State's capacities to organize, recuperate, even produce social forces. Michel Foucault's work has made dear that the institutions and _enfermements_ or enclosures of civil society - the church, the school, the prison, the family, the union, the party, et cetera - constitute the paradigmatic terrain for the disciplinary deployments of power in modern society, producing normalized subjects and thus exerting hegemony through consent in a way that is perhaps more subtle but no less authoritarian than the exertion of dictatorship through coercion. The disciplinary perspective, then, might recognize the same channels passing through civil society, but sees the flows moving argain in the opposite direction. ... The social dialectic thus functions in order that antagonistic social forces be subsumed within the prior and unitary synthesis of the State.

... Hegel's understanding of the historical rise of civil society and the generalization of its educative social role does correspond in several respects to the process that Michel Foucault calls the governmentalization of the State. The State of sovereignty which, according to Foucault, served as the dominant form of rule in Europe from the Middle Ages to the sixteenth century, positioned itself as a transcendent singularity with respect to its subjects. The transcendence of the sovereign State afforded it a certain detachment from the pressures of conflictive particular interests in society. In the passage to the modern State, however, the transcendence and singularity of the State were overturned through the rise of what Foucault calls В»governmentality.В« The rule of the governmental State is characterized instead by its immanence to the population through a multiplicity of forms. ... The management of people and things implied by this governance involves an active engagement, exchange, or dialectic among social forces and between social forces and the State. The same educative social processes that Hegel casts in terms of abstraction and organization, Foucault recognizes in terms of training, discipline, and management. The channels or striae in which these processes function, recognized as social institutions by Hegel, are characterized by Foucault in terms of deployments (_dispositifs_) and enclosures (_enfermements_). Civil society, from this perspective, is the productive site of modern economy (economy understood now in the large sense); in other words, it is the site of the production of goods, desires, individual and collective identities, et cetera. It is the site, finally, of the institutional dialectic of social forces, of the social dialectic that gives rise to and underwrites the State.

In his extensive work on the nature of power, however, Foucault not only refuses Gramsci's inversion of the priority between civil society and political society (that is, civil society and the State), he goes one step further and argues that we can make no analytical distinction at all between them. When Foucault argues that power cannot be isolated but is everywhere, that it comes from everywhere, that there is no outside to power, he is also denying the analytical separation of political society from civil society. ... In the disciplinary and governmental society the lines of power extend through social space in the channels created by the institutions of civil society. The exertion of power is organized through deployments, which are at once ideological, institutional, and corporeal. This is not to say that there is no State, but rather that it cannot effectively be isolated and contested at a level separate from society. ... On the contrary, the State as such is better understood as the result, the consolidation or molarization of forces of В»statizationВ« (_etatisation_) immanent to social power relations. The causes and intentions that inform and order power relations are not isolated in some headquarters of rationality but are immanent to the field of forces. Foucault thus prefers to use instead of _State_ the term _government_, which indicates the multiplicity and immanence of the forces of statization to the social field. ... In particular, Foucault emphasizes the В»educationalВ« aspect of civil society whereby particular social interests are enlightened to the general interest and brought in line with the universal. Education means discipline. More accurately, Foucault reformulates the educational process of civil society in terms of production: power acts not only by training or ordering the elements of the social terrain but actually by producing them - producing desires, needs, individuals, identities, et cetera. ... The State, Hegel claims, is not the result but the cause; Foucault adds, not a transcendent but an immanent cause, statization, immanent to the various channels, institutions, or enclosures of social production.

... Disciplinary society can be characterized as civil society seen from a different perspective, approached from underneath, from the microphysics of its power relations. While Gramsci highlights the democratic potentials of the institutions of civil society, Foucault makes clear that civil society is a society founded on discipline and that the education it offers is a diffuse network of normalization. From this perspective, Gramsci and Foucault highlight the two contrasting faces of Hegel's civil society. ...

Infinite Undulations of the Snake

When we look at the contemporary societies of Western Europe and North America, it seems that these various, rich, promising, and frightening theoretical visions of civil society, both in the Hegelian version and in the Gramscian and Foucauldian reformulations, no longer hold - they no longer grasp the dominant mechanisms or schema of social production and social ordering. The decline of the paradigm of civil society correlates to a passage in contemporary society toward a new configuration of social relations and new conditions of rule. This is not to say that the forms and structures of social exchange, participation, and domination that were identified by the concept of civil society have ceased entirely to exist, but rather that they have been displaced from the dominant position by a new configuration of apparatuses, deployments, and structures. Deleuze's notion [that we have recently experienced a passage from a disciplinary society to a society of control] can serve us here as a first attempt to understand the decline of the rule of civil society and the rise of a new form of control. Disciplinary societies, as I suggested earlier, are characterized by the enclosures or institutions that serve as the skeleton or backbone of civil society; these enclosures define the striae of social space. ... Deleuze insists, however, that these social enclosures or institutions are today everywhere in crisis [and] suggests that it is more adequate, then, to understand the collapse of the walls defined by the enclosures not as some sort of social evacuation but rather as the generalization of logics that previously functioned within these limited domains across the entire society, spreading like a virus. The logic of capitalist production perfected in the factory now invests all forms of social production. The same might he said also for the school, the family, the hospital, and the other disciplinary institutions. ... Social space has not been emptied of the disciplinary institutions; it has been completely filled with the modulations of control. The relationship between society and the State no longer primarily involves the mediation and organization of the institutions for discipline and rule. Instead, the relationship sets the State in motion directly through the perpetual circuitry of social production.

We should be careful to point out, however, that the passage from disciplinary society to the society of control is not merely a shift in the institutional structures of rule. ... What underlies the various institutions is the diagram: the anonymous or abstract strategic machine, the unformed or nonstratified schema of power relations. The diagram transcends, or better subtends the various institutional assemblages. ... The disciplinary diagram runs throughout the various institutions defining the conditions of possibility, the conditions of what can be seen, said, and known, the conditions of the exertion of power. The passage to a society of control, then, will certainly manifest symptoms at the institutional level, but it should he grasped also and above all at the diagrammatic level. If we are to follow Foucault's method, then, we should ask, first, what are the diagrams that define the conditions of possibility in the societies of control? And then, in what kinds of social assemblages will these diagrammatic forces be consolidated, and how? The metaphors available to us can at least give us an indication of the nature of this passage. ... The panopticon, and disciplinary diagrammatics in general, functioned primarily in terms of positions, fixed points, and identities. ... The diagram of control, however, is not oriented toward position and identity, but rather toward mobility and anonymity. It functions on the basis of В»the whatever,В« the flexible and mobile performance of contingent identities, and thus its assemblages or institutions are elaborated primarily through repetition and the production of simulacra. ... Elaborate controls over information flow, extensive use of polling and monitoring techniques, and innovative social use of the media thus gain prominent positions in the exertion of power. ...

Claiming the decline of civil sociey, of course, does not mean that all the mechanisms of rule and organization which characterized civil society no longer exist or function. Similarly, recognizing a passage from disciplinary societies to societies of control does not mean that disciplinary deployments and the attendant potentialities of resistance have completely disappeared. Disciplinary deployments remain, as do elements of sovereignty in the regimes of control. ... What is primarily at issue, though, is not simply the existence of certain apparatuses, mechanisms, or deployments, but rather their predominance within a specific paradigm of rule. Our task is to discern the salient characteristics of the social formation that succeeds civil society; the smooth spaces of the societies of control constitute our first attempt. We can formulate a second, complementary approach to this problematic by casting the passage not in Foucauldian but rather in Marxian terminology, which will highlight the contemporary change in the social organization of labor. ... Marx recognized the passage from the formal to the real subsumption in nineteenth-century society as a tendency, but it seems to me that this passage has only come to be generalized in the most completely capitalist countries in our times. [6] According to Marx, in the first of these two phases, the formal subsumption, social labor processes are subsumed under capital; that is, they are enveloped within the capitalist relations of production in such a manner that capital intervenes as the director or manager. In this arrangement, capital subsumes labor the way it finds it; capital takes over existing labor processes that were developed in previous modes of production or at any rate outside of capitalist production. .... Actually, as Hegel clearly recognized in his writings ... capital cannot directly integrate concrete labor but must first abstract it from its concrete forms. The various processes of abstraction, the resistances these give rise to, and the potential lines of social conflict between concrete labor and abstract labor are thus principle characteristics of the phase of the formal subsumption. Capital tends, however, through the socialization of production and through scientific and technological innovation, to create new labor processes and to destroy old ones, transforming the situations of the various agents of production. Capital thus sets in motion a specifically capitalist mode of production. Marx calls the subsumption of labor _real_, then, when the labor processes themselves are born within capital and therefore when labor is incorporated not as an external, but an internal force, proper to capital itself. As we move to the phase of the real subsumption, Marx explains, labor processes evolve so that, first of all, production is no longer a direct and individual activitv but an immediately social activity. ... In the _specifically_ capitalist mode of production, that is, in the phase of the real subsumption, productive labor - or even production in general - no longer appears as the pillar that defines and sustains capitalist social organization. Production is given an objective quality, as if the capitalist system were a machine that marched forward on its own accord, without labor, a capitalist automaton. ... This is how we should understand the passage from the formal to the real subsumption. The society of the formal subsumption was characterized by the dialectic between capital and labor: as a foreign force subsumed within capital, labor had to be abstracted, recuperated, disciplined, and tamed within the productive processes. But labor nonetheless was continually recognized as the source of all social wealth. ... In the society of the real subsumption this dialectic no longer holds the central role, and capital no longer needs to engage labor or represent labor at the heart of production. What is subsumed, what is accepted into the process, is no longer a potentially conflictive force but a product of the system itself; the real subsumption does not extend vertically throughout the various strata of society but rather constructs a separate plane, a simulacrum of society that excludes or marginalizes social forces foreign to the system. Social capital thus appears to reproduce itself autonomously, as if it were emancipated from the working class, and labor becomes invisible in the system. ...

... The State of the real subsumption is no longer interested in mediation or В»educationВ« but in separation, no longer in discipline but in control. The State of the real subsumption operates on a separate plane, a simulacrum of the social field, abstract from labor itself. ... Once again, my general point here is simply that in this passage the democratic and/or disciplinary institutions of civil society, the channels of social mediation, as a particular form of the organization of social labor, society politically have declined and been displaced from the center of the scene. Not the State, but civil society has withered away! In other words, even if one were to consider civil society politically desirable ... the social conditions necessary for civil society no longer exist.

The Postcivil Condition

... Civil society, as we have seen, is central to a form of rule, or government, as Foucault says, that focuses, on the one hand, on the identitv of the citizen and the processes of civilization and, on the other hand, on the organization of abstract labor. These processes are variously conceived as education, training, or discipline, but what remains common is the active engagement with social forces (through either mediation or production) to order social identities within the context of institutions. What has come to an end, or more accurately declined in importance in postcivil society, then, are precisely these functions of mediation or education and the institutions that gave them form. The formulation _postcivil_ however, like _postmodern_, is finally limited by its backward gaze; it is too reactive to do justice to the new paradigm of social relations. More important than the social elements and techniques that have faded from prominence are those that have newly taken the dominant positions. The deployments of control and the social constitution of the real subsumption give us a framework to begin to grasp the novelties of our situation. Instead of disciplining the citizen as a fixed social identity, the new social regime seeks to control the citizen as a whatever identity, or rather as an infinitely flexible placeholder for identity. It tends to establish an autonomous plane of rule, a simulacrum of the social - separate from the terrain of conflictive social forces. Mobility, speed, and flexibility are the qualities that characterize this separate plane of rule. The infinitely programmable machine, the ideal of cybernetics, gives us at least on approximation of the diagram of the new paradigm of rule. Analyzing the new techniques, of social control is only worthwhile to the extent that it allows us to grasp also the new potentialities for contestation and freedom emerging witthin this new paradigm. ... I would suggest that in order to begin thinking these new potentialities we should return again to investigate the form and nature of labor, or creative social practices, in contemporary society. ... Social practices have certainly changed and so too should our notion of what constitutes labor - not just in the sphere of wage labor (which indeed has undergone radical transformation in some sectors) but also in the sphere of desiring production, intellectual creativitv, caring labor, kin work, and so forth. ... Even in the society of control, labor is still the В»savage beastВ« that Hegel feared, refusing to he subjugated and tamed - and perhaps its potential is even greater today when it is no longer engaged, mediated, and disciplined through the institutions of civil society as it was in the previous paradigm. The networks of sociality and forms of cooperation embedded in contemporary social practices constitute the germs for a new movement, with new forms of contestation and new conceptions of lliberation. This alternative community of social practices (call it, perhaps, the self-organization of concrete lahor) will be the most potent challenge to the control of postcivil society, and will point, perhaps, to the of our future.

------

От Пуденко Сергей
К Пуденко Сергей (06.01.2006 17:31:15)
Дата 06.01.2006 22:19:38

"Ибимат". Становление Becoming-Intense Becomig Animal, Becoming Woman...


> 1) спецкурс по теме Ибимата (много) и

> 2) - развитие темы "общества Контроля" (первая статья Делеза "Контроль
и Становление" - в Альманахе и на первой странице сайта)
>
> -----
http://www.protevi.com/john/DG/

> ------
Тысяча Плато, глава 10

Один из центральных моментов Ибимата. Принципиально "ортогональный"
процесс к простому "развитию" как "росту". Становление ребенок-
взрослый,девочка-женщина -эмерджентный процесс, вовлекающий "встречи" и
сугубо индивидуальный. Но в то же время -закономерный.
Другой тип. "Становление животным" (молекулярный тип процесса).
Все это не метафоры.
Общая теория "интенсивностей" (потоков, мощностей) практически та же,
что и научная версия теории -Побиск.

Рассматриваются на основе древних концепций - "здесьность" (thisness)
по Иоганну Дунс Скотту и главное,по теории аффектов Спинозы. Делез тут
основывается на своем решении проблемы интеллект-аффект, центрального
пункта системы Спинозы. Подробней - в спецкурсе лекций Делеза в Винсенне
(полностью выложены в сети)

Дальнейшие ходы - на главы Тысяча Плато : "Micropolitics", "Захват",
"Машина войны"

Дальнейшее чтение. Рекомендуется чтение на любителя по отдельным
направлениям. Напр. В чем суть становления женщиной и т.д. Откуда это
"внимание феминизма" к Ибимату...

наберите "Becoming Cat, Becoming Irena" в поисковике. вообще,
делезовский Интернет дает почти все необходимое

( Недавно эту вторую после Машины Войны центральную 10 главу ТП -
Becomig Animal, Becoming Intense.... разбирали у нас на семинаре - есть
аудио,будет текст - выложу)



Опять к сож. по английски

Some Remarks on Plateau 10: Becoming-Intense ....


Comments and Questions to: {John Protevi}
{LSU French Studies}
{Protevi Home Page}



1.The key term of Plateau 10, devenir, is one of the relatively few
cases where the translation of D/G into English is problematic.
Relatively few, that is, compared with the absolute necessity of reading
Derrida or Irigaray in French, for instance. This is due to three
factors: 1) D/G's insistence on the primacy of the concept (philosophy
is the creation of concepts, they declare in What is Philosophy?); 2)
their disdain of treating language in terms of signifiers; 3) their
abjuring of "typographical cleverness, lexical agility, ... syntactical
boldness" [22E/33F] in favor of a method that will construct the
multiple. As they say in a famous passage a little earlier in the
"Rhizome" plateau: "It is not enough to say 'Long live the multiple' ...
No typographical, lexical or even syntactical cleverness is enough to
make it heard. The multiple must be made [Le multiple, il faut le
faire]" (6E/13F). Other examples of translation difficulties would
include, as Massumi notes: puissance vs. pouvoir, which we will deal
with later, and signifiance and йnoncй, which we wrestled with the last
few weeks.

Devenir is the infinitive form of the verb. Infinitive means unlimited,
without temporal or logical restriction, that is, without a "tense" or a
"mood." Now French can use the infinitive form as a noun: un devenir; "a
to-become" or un кtre, "a to-be." English, obviously cannot do this, so
Massumi translates devenir with "becoming." "Becoming," on the other
hand, is in some cases a gerund, a verbal that functions as a noun: "a
becoming" or in other cases a present participle, a verb form that
functions as part of a verb phrase: "the wasp is becoming the orchid,"
or as a modifier: "the wasp, becoming the orchid ..." In these latter
cases of becoming as a present participle, there is a temporal
restriction to the present.

This is important to recognize because, as Deleuze/Guattari explains at
MP 263E/322F, an infinitive, even though it is not temporally
restricted, is not "indeterminate" with regard to time; rather it
expresses the "floating, nonpulsed time proper to Aeon, in other words,
the time of the pure event or of becoming." Deleuze/Guattari explains
that the plane of consistency, the virtual realm of continuous
variation, the BwO, has both a specific plane of content: haecceities or
assemblages of unformed matters and pure functions or affects; and a
specific plane of expression: indefinite article + proper name +
infinitive verb. We thus have a clue as to "becoming": it is an event, a
bifurcation, the actualization of which moves a system from one zone of
its phase space to another.

2. Deleuze/Guattari will tell us outright how to think devenir: it is a
"mutual but dissymetric deterritorialization" (Dialogues 77F); it is the
entry into a "symbiosis" (MP 238E/291F); the production of a new
assemblage (257-8E/315F). What is real is the "the becoming itself, the
block of becoming, not the supposedly fixed terms through which that
which becomes passes" (238E/291F). Let's take their favorite example,
the wasp-orchid. The orchid becomes necessary to the life of the wasp
and vice versa: what is primary is the new assemblage, the wasp-orchid
machine. The becoming of wasp-orchid does not have a subject separate
from itself: it's not that the wasp, say, stays the same and merely adds
a new property to the set of properties that defines it. Nor is there a
goal or finish (or "term" = terminus) separate from the block of
becoming, for the other in the pair is also changed by its entry into
the new assemblage. In complexity theory terms, the new assemblage, the
symbiosis, is marked by emergent properties above and beyond the sum of
the parts. It is also important to remember that a becoming is a
combination of heterogenous parts; it is an alliance rather than a
filiation, an "unnatural participation," a "marriage against nature," a
"transversal communication." Keith Ansell Pearson cites Lynn Margulis'
revolutionary work in contemporary biology on mitochondrial capture as
the origin of the eukaryotic (nucleated) cells as a heterogenous
becoming, a symbiosis that produces a new assemblage (Viroid Life,
132)..

3. A few words on "becoming" in two of its most important instances in
the history of philosophy.

A. Hegel's Science of Logic begins with the triad:
Being-Nothing-Becoming [Sein-Nichts-Werden]. The first, most general and
most abstract thought possible is that of pure being, pure immediacy, or
pure intuition with no determination whatsoever. But this thought is
also precisely the thought of nothing at all: it is the pure form of
thought with no content whatsoever. But this thought of nothing can not
be held onto either and the thought then moves to Becoming. We thus
recognize that Being, pure self-identity, and its absolute opposite,
Nothing, are interchangeable. This sameness means we can never isolate
being and nothing, for they have always already gone over into each
other: "What is the truth is neither being nor nothing, but that
being--does not pass over but has passed over--into nothing, and nothing
into being." (83/82-83). As Gadamer shows, the "always already" of "has
passed over" [ьbergegangen ist] indicates the circularity of the system.
Spirit is always on the move, the movement generated by an originary
splitting (being and nothing are opposites) that is always already a
healing (being and nothing are the same). The sameness of being and
nothing is not self-identity as simple undifferentiation, but as the
always already accomplished disappearance into each other of what is
absolutely different. Becoming, then is the basic movement of Hegel's
Logic, and thus of thought and nature and spirit, the elements of the
system

But just what purchase on real becoming does one gain by examining pure
thought (or pure consciousness, the correlate of pure thought which
Hegel examines in the Phenomenology of Spirit)? None at all, Deleuze
writes. Michael Hardt has pointed out that Deleuze's early Bergson work
is the locus of Deleuze's working through of his hatred of Hegel.
Deleuze writes in
Bergsonism: "To Bergson, it seems that in this type of dialectical
method one begins with concepts that, like baggy clothes, are much too
big. The One in general, the multiple in general, nonbeing in general
... of what use is a dialectic that believes itself to be reunited with
the real when it compensates for the inadequacy of a concept that is too
broad or too general by invoking
the opposite concept, which is no less broad and general? ... The
singular will never be attained by correcting a generality with another
generality" (44E).

B. Nietzsche contrasts Being and Becoming. While Deleuze and D/G are
obviously more sympathetic to Nietzsche than to Hegel, Nietzsche's
concept of Becoming is not that which animates Plateau 10. For
Nietzsche, Being is the privilege of stability over change, of substance
over event. Becoming is the insistence on the "eventualizing" of
substance: rather than being a
substance with properties all things are events of capture and escape,
the outcome of struggles of forces against each other, struggles that
are stabilized in relations of power via a process of "interpretation."
Now for Nietzsche, a substance with properties is a fiction produced by
the "metaphysics of grammar," that is, a projection of the subject --
predicate structure of Indo-European languages onto the inhabitants of
the world, so that they are seen as substances with predicates.
(Although it is possible to give more interesting readings of him, I
have to admit that Aristotle's text can yield a prime example of the
analogy between the structures of language and reality: this analogy is
reflected in the term logos: language, logic, ratio, structure of the
world.)

The metaphysics of grammar is at root a phenomenon of a weak will that
separates a force from that it can do: the weak "could have" been
strong, but they "chose" not to-thus the sin of the strong is not their
strength, but their acting on their strength. This separates a subject
underneath of action. For Nietzsche, a force goes to the limit of its
strength: or at least that is the definition of nobility. In any event,
Nietzschean Becoming is much too much a cosmic concept for D/G's use in
this plateau, where it designates the most concrete of actions.

4. Spinoza. The real philosophical heritage upon which D/G draw in the
central "ontology" section of plateau 10 is Spinoza. There is a brief
mention of Bergson early in the plateau during the discussion of blocks
of becoming, but let's defer any discussion of Bergson to a later
meeting.

Deleuze's two works on Spinoza are marvels. Expressionism in Philosophy:
Spinoza was Deleuze's submission to the jury for his doctorat d'кtat in
1968; Spinoza: Practical Philosophy is a little gem, the work in which
Deleuze's love for the object of his writing shines forth most clearly.
Deleuze is extravagant in his praise of Spinoza in his interviews and
writings: "the prince
of philosophers"; "the Christ of philosophy" (to which Alain Badiou,
whose Deleuze: Le clameur de l'кtre is the most challenging of the
recent French reactions to Deleuze [along with Alliez, Mengue,
Zourabichvili], adds that Deleuze was "one of his most considerable
apostles" [150]).

Reading Spinoza's Ethics (Demonstrated by the Order of Geometry) is
without a doubt one of the most exhilarating experiences available to
students of western philosophy. Deleuze sets a passage from Bernard
Malamud's The Fixer as the epigraph to Spinoza: Pratical Philosophy. In
it, a poor and poorly educated man explains to a judge how he felt upon
reading Spinoza: "I found it in a junkyard in a nearby town, paid a
kopek and left cursing myself for wasting money hard to come by. Later I
read through a few pages and kept on going as though there were a
whirlwind at my back. As I say, I didn't understand every word, but when
you're dealing with such ideas you feel as though you were taking a
witch's ride. After that I wasn't the same man ..." (The feeling I had
reading Anti-Oedipus for the first time!).

What draws Deleuze to Spinoza? Immanence. Spinoza refuses all
transcendence. His single substance, Deus sive Natura (God or Nature, an
equivalence) saturates existence. Its two attributes (or more precisely,
the two attributes accessible to us) thought and extension, are, because
immanent to the same substance, univocal expressions of that substance.
Spinoza thus refuses the reserve of negative theology (the substance
saturates the world with no reserve) and the analogical being of
positive theologies that propose a transcendent God (God/Nature is fully
expressed in its attributes; there is no supereminence to God's being in
relation to the being of thought and extension in the world). In D/G
terms, God/Nature is a plane of consistency or desiring-production
itself as the being of the world.

Spinoza's theory of bodies is also very attractive to Deleuze. Bodies
for Spinoza are assemblages: Part II, Proposition 13, Definition: "When
any given bodies of the same or different magnitude are compelled by
other bodies to remain in contact, or if they be moved at the same of
different rates of speed, so that their mutual movements should preserve
among themselves a certain fixed relation, we say that such bodies are
in union, and that together they compose one body or individual, which
is distinguished from other bodies by this union." Notice that bodies
are not composed of definite types of stuff, but by achieved
relationships of speed or rest. Earlier Spinoza writes: "Bodies are
distinguished from one another in respect of motion and rest, quickness
and slowness, and not in respect of substance" (II P13 Lemma I). We see
D/G explicating this notion of body in "Memories of a Spinozist I." A
body is composed: it is an assemblage of parts whose relative motions
are able to be preserved for a time in a ratio of capture and escape,
deterritorialization and reterritorialization. D/G call this the
"longitude" of a body (256E/313F).

"Memories of a Spinozist II" deals with "latitude," which is the set of
affects of a body, the set of actions of which it is capable. "Affects
are becomings," D/G write: affects are the set of incorporeal
transformations, the bifurcations that move a body into a different
region of its phase space, that is, that allow it to enter new
assemblages, new forms of interminglings with other bodies to form new
machines. As capacities, affects are virtual or intensive as opposed to
the extensive parts that form the longitude of a body. Affects are "what
a body can do" (Deleuze loves to quote Spinoza to the effect that "we do
not know what the body is capable of" -- we do not know [a priori], and
hence we must experiment. Defining bodies by affects is not the same as
by genus/species (this relies on the substance-properties model).
Grouping bodies by affects breaks open the organic stratum to the
"machinic phylum" that cuts across it: for example, a race horse has
more in common with a race car or speed boat than with a plow horse,
which is closer to an ox than to the race horse.

In "Memories of a Haecceity," D/G bring the two previous Spinozist
points together: "On the PC, a body is defined only by a longitude and a
latitude." This mode of individuation is called by D/G haecceity,
recalling Duns Scotus' use of the term for singular being. A haecceity
is an assemblage, a certain relation of particles in motion or rest
giving rise to a set of affects. This is an individuation, but not that
of a subject or substance. Examples are "five in the evening" or a life:
a set of matters and functions on a PC individuated from others on that
PC. Here we see a theme familiar to us from our study of the Geology of
Morals: D/G's insistence that the virtual is not chaos but is inhabited
by its own denizens. This refuses the transcendence or chaos forced
choice (Louis XVI: "aprиs nous, le dйluge"). The time of the PC is Aeon,
as we remarked at the beginning of the lecture.

D/G do not detail it here, but Spinoza's ethics and politics are
fascinating. (Here I rely on Michael Hardt, Gilles Deleuze: An
Apprenticeship in Philosophy [Minnesota, 1993], a model of clarity.) The
train of thought is the following. Affects can be either passive
(external cause) or active (internal cause). Encounters with others
produce either joy or sadness, depending on whether the other body is
composable with ours, that is, whether the new assemblage results in an
increase or diminution of our
strength. So we can have either passive sad or joyful encounters or
active joyful or sad encounters. Spinoza's realism makes him say that
most of our encounters are passive sad. But we do have the principle of
selection: move to the active and the joyful. Spinozist politics is
arranging a system of joyful encounters that tend to more activity and
more joy. This is only possible
through the puissance of democracy rather than the pouvoir of the State,
which precisely relies on the multiplication of sad passions, as D/G
recall for us in Anti-Oedipus in quoting Spinoza: the prime question of
political philosophy: how can desire desire its own repression? "Why do
men fight for their servitude as stubbornly as though it were their
salvation?" (AO 29) How can people possibly reach the point of shouting:
"More taxes! Less bread!"

In the insistence on joy rather than pleasure we see a key difference
between D/G and Foucault. For D/G pleasure is the subjective
appropriation of the shared energy field that is joy, while for
Foucault, pleasure is the (notorious) rallying cry for resistance to
bio-power and the dispositif of sexuality at the close of History of
Sexuality I: "bodies and pleasures." (Resistance to power, by the way,
is the other major difference: for D/G, the line of flight is primary,
and power relations
are secondary phenomena of reterritorialization; hence resistance is
reactive.)



-------

process is the subject of the two memories of a Spinozist sections. I
think it's correct to say that at one end of this process of composition
is the haecceities; they are more or less the raw material, the
heterogeneous elements that enter into the process of composition. Now,
the term haecceity comes from the work of Duns Scotus, the Scottish
scholastic philosopher (14th century?) and specifically from his book on
individuation. I think haecceity can be used interchangeable, at least
in the context of scholastic philosophy, with the term singularity. A
haecceity, D&G explain, is a mode of individuation very different from a
person, a subject, a thing, or a substance. A haecceity might refer
rather to a season, a time of day, a wind. The light at that hour, or
that color was singular. It cannot be captured in its difference from
something else, but is only defined in its thisness. (The recourse to
"thisness" or to the "here and now" are often used to understand Duns
Scotus's use of the term.) D&G of course explain it somewhat
differently. "They are haecceities in the sense that they consist
entirely of relations of movement and rest between molecules or
particules, capacities to affect and be affected" (261). Or, in their
terms they consist of longitude (relations of movement and rest) and
latitude (powers of affect). (I have no idea why the words longitude and
latitude are used.) This definition of haecceities as longitude and
latitude demonstrates how they are available or disposed to the process
of composition. On one hand, and this according to Spinoza's definition
of the Individual in the Ethics, an Individual is composed of bodies
that have a common relationship of movement and rest (that is the
longitude part). And on the other hand, (and now in terms of latitude),
the affects of each body, including both its power to act and its power
to be affected, determine a different axis of composition. This has to
do with the Spinoza line Deleuze likes so much: we still don't know what
a body can do. What it can do indicates how it can be composed. "We know
nothing about a body until we know what it can do, in other words, what
its affects are, how they can or cannot enter into composition with
other affects, with the affects of other bodies, either to destroy that
body or to be destroyed by it..." (257). What interests me in these two
axes, longitude and latitude, is that they begin to identify how the
process of composition can take place.